It is well-known that the cartesian product of two infinite sets of cardinality
is also of cardinality .
Equivalently, the set
can be well-ordered in order-type
. However, the standard ordering on
does
not work, since it is always of order type .
Instead, we introduce for each ordinal
the canonical well-ordering of as follows:
if either
or
but
precedes lexicographically. If we note
the ordinal isomorphic to that well-ordering ordering,
then we can prove that as wanted
(see Corollary 0.4).
Jech’s Set Theory
book contains several properties of . For example,
is increasing : for any ordinal ,
is a (proper) initial segment of
and of
for any limit ordinal . As a consequence,
which can also trivially
be seen by the increasing function from
to . Also,
implies .
This can not be a strict equality,
or otherwise the element
corresponding to via the
isomorphism between and
would be an element larger than all for .
Hence is continuous and by exercise 2.7 of the same
book, has arbitrary large fixed points. Exercise 3.5 shows that
and so does not increase
cardinality (see Corollary 0.2 for a much
better upper bound).
Hence starting at any infinite cardinal the construction
of exercise 2.7 provides infinitely many fixed points of having
cardinality . Hence the infinite fixed points of are not just
cardinals and we can wonder what they are exactly…
I recently tried to solve Exercise I.11.7 of Kunen’s Set Theory book which
suggests a nice characterization of infinite fixed points of :
they are the ordinals of the form . However, I could not
find a simple proof of this statement so instead I tried to determine the
explicit expression of , from which the result becomes obvious
(see Corollary 0.3).
My final calculation is summarized in Theorem 0.1, which provides
a relatively nice expression of . Recall that any
can be written uniquely as
where is (following Kunen’s terminology)
the “logarithm in base of ” (that we
will denote for )
and are the quotient and
remainder of the Euclidean division of by . Alternatively,
this can be seen from Cantor’s Normal Form: and are the exponent
and coefficient of the largest term while is the sum of terms of smaller
exponents.
Theorem 0.1.
For all ordinal , we denote the order-type of
the canonical ordering of . Then can be
calculated as follows:
1.
Finite Ordinals:
For any we have
2.
Limit Ordinals:
For any limit ordinal ,
(a)
If does not
divide then
(b)
Otherwise, we write
for some . If
then
(like the first case but we “decrement in the second factor”)
(c)
Otherwise, and
we write
for some . We have
(like the first case but we “decrement in the second factor”)
3.
Infinite Successor Ordinals:
For any limit ordinal and we have
where is determined as in the previous point.
Proof.
In a future blog post ;-) ∎
From this theorem, we deduce several corollaries:
Corollary 0.2.
For any ordinal , we have
where is the remainder in the Euclidean division
of by (i.e. the constant term in the Cantor Normal Form).
Proof.
The “Limit Ordinals” case is i.e. ,
which is readily seen by the
previous theorem.
Then we deduce for the “Infinite Successor Ordinals” case:
where and
.
Since we can write
. ∎
Hence the order type of the canonical ordering of
(i.e. ) is never
significantly bigger than the one of the standard lexical ordering
(i.e. ), and even never larger
for limit ordinals. Moreover, for many ordinals
the canonical ordering is of order type :
Corollary 0.3.
The fixed points of are and for
all ordinals .
Proof.
For the “Finite Ordinals” case, we have iff or
. For the “Infinite Successor Ordinals” case, we have
if so .
Now we look at the three subcases of the “Limit Ordinals” case. For the
first one, we have
and so .
For the second one, we note that
and so
(compare the Cantor Normal Form).
Since by assumption, we have .
Similarly in the third case, if we expand the parenthesis the first term
is raised to the power
which is stricly greater than
if .
Now if , we obtain and
. Hence if
and if .
Finally for , iff
iff
for some ordinal . ∎
Finally, now that we know that infinite fixed points of are of the
form we only need to verify that infinite
cardinals are of this form to prove that
. This provides an alternative
(less straightforward) proof of Theorem 3.5 from Jech’s Set Theory book.
Corollary 0.4.
Any infinite cardinal is a fixed point of .
Hence for any infinite cardinal we have
Proof.
For any cardinal infinite cardinal that is a fixed point of ,
the canonical well-ordering provides a bijection between and
i.e. .
Hence if are two fixed points, we have
Suppose that there is a cardinal which is not a fixed point of
and consider the smallest one.
Then any infinite cardinal below is a fixed point of
and the previous equality is still true below .
Suppose and
write where
corresponds to the remaining terms in Cantor Normal Form. Then
,
and . But the two first
relations imply
which contradicts the third one.
Hence .
Now suppose
and write
where
corresponds to the remaining terms in Cantor Normal Form. Then we have
where and
since
is strictly increasing. Then
, and . But
again, the two first relations imply which contradicts the third one.
Finally,
and so is a fixed point
of , a contradiction. Hence all the infinite cardinals are
fixed point of and so the property stated at the beginning is
true for arbitrary infinite cardinals . ∎